This is a major and salutary departure from historical practice, but what remains of the definition? SWGFAST’s last definition of “individualization” was “[t]he determination by an examiner that there is sufficient quality and quantity of detail in agreement to conclude that two friction ridge impressions originated from the same source.” SWGFAST, Standard Terminology of Friction Ridge Examination (Latent/Tenprint), Mar. 13, 2013, at 5. “If two friction ridge impressions originated from the same source,” however, they did not originate from any other source, that is, from any “other human[] in the world.”11.2.2. The SWGFAST Individualization/Identification Position Statement (Document #103) states that: “The ability of a latent print examiner to individualize a single latent impression, with the implication that they have definitely excluded all other humans in the world, is not supported by research and was removed from SWGFAST’s definition of individualization.”
The only interpretation of the Guideline that seems to make sense is that an “individualization” is a tentative rather than a “definitive” conclusion that all other humans in the world have been excluded. Indeed, the Guideline continues:
But it is easier to say what should not be said than to prescribe what should be stated. The Guideline offers the following positive-plus-negative advice:11.2.3. Specific words and phrases conveying absolute certainty are inappropriate or misleading and should not be used to express conclusions. Specific problematic phrases include: [e]xclusion of all others, 100% certainty (as an absolute fact), [and z]ero error rate / infallible method.
Evidently, the examiner should say something like "My decision is that X is the source of the latent print. I base this decision on my training and experience. I have [enormous? high? medium? low?] confidence in my personal decision." Of course, if a categorical conclusion is given, what the judge or jury would like to hear is the probability that this conclusion is correct, not that an examiner has some personal belief. But how a latent print examiner could provide such a posterior probability without considering a case-specific prior probability is an unsolved problem. A more measurable quantity is a conditional error probability—here, the probability that an examiner would identify X when X is not the source. Although some experiments have examined the rate of false positive (and negative) errors by latent print examiners, the Guideline does not propose using these figures.11.2.4. These concepts should rather be expressed as the conclusion of the examiner, based upon data observed and interpreted through the examiner’s training and experience. The examiner has a level of personal confidence associated with the accuracy and reliability of this conclusion; however, the accuracy and precision of this personal level of confidence cannot currently be measured and reported. For this reason, certainty should not be reported numerically or in absolute terms.
Instead, it implies in the future it will be possible "to measure a personal level of confidence." I suppose an examiner could be forced to pick the probability at which he or she is indifferent to a gamble in a game of chance that has a well-defined probability for winning and losing. Would that make the personal confidence measurable? If so, why can't it be done currently?
In any event, the lack of a workable mechanism to measure personal confidence is not why claims of absolute certainty should be avoided. The reason is that nothing empirical is absolutely certain. Tomorrow, the laws of physics could change and heavy objects could float upward.
Neither does the difficulty of devising a suitable psychometric instrument for personal certainty explain why an examiner cannot report any numbers. People quantify personal judgments that cannot be measured objectively when their doctors ask them to report the severity of pain on a scale of 1 to ten. Why cannot an examiner report a defensible level of confidence numerically if the subjective precision is provided? E.g., “I think X is the source, and the strength of my belief is 9 on a scale of 1-10, but obviously this is not an exact number. I could have said 8, or even 7 as well, but I would not want to go below that.”
I am not arguing that examiners should grade their personal belief in a source attribution on a scale of 1-10 or express it as a numerical probability. My point merely is that SWGFAST's argument about reporting a number for relative certainty is superficial and underdeveloped.
No comments:
Post a Comment